Sovereignty and Possession in the English New World: The Legal Foundations of Empire, 1576–1640

Ken MacMillan
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2006, ISBN: 9780521870092; 250pp.; Price: £50.00
American Bar Foundation (Chicago)
https://reviews.history.ac.uk/review/597
Date accessed: 6 June, 2023
As social history’s highest tides recede, certain of its presumptions are exposed for reargument. In the case of the early-modern Atlantic, one such comes in the shape of Karen Ordahl Kupperman’s long-held view that the decisive truths of England’s first New World colonizings are properly learned from the autoptically authoritative settler—‘the English who actually spent time with Americans’(1). The contention breeds two consequences: first, confronted by the ‘truths’ of the eyewitness, the metropolis’s texts of colonizing (its geographies and chorographies, its maps and charters, treatises and instructions) become ‘false’—or at best empirically unfounded speculations, armchair fantasies; secondly, historical inquiry becomes oriented to producing the experiential moment in which the encounter between settler and colonized object actually occurs. Here lies the fount of authenticity, the contact point that identifies what is to be explained and provides the evidence. Thus are set down markers that peg the historian’s subject in historical time. Measured by the first moment of encounter, England came late to colonizing. John Wood Sweet writes in his introduction to the recent Kupperman-inflected essay collection, Envisioning an English Empire, that, ‘it was only around the 1580s that the horizons of English leaders, merchants, intellectuals, and adventurers began to broaden’(2).
Why would one argue with a literature that has achieved so much? After all, it is not that long since the settler eye-witnesses invoked by historians saw nothing but others like themselves doing nothing but building Englishness anew on the edges of a spacious emptiness that they would later penetrate and ‘modernize’ (3). Into their midst Kupperman and her peers tersely inserted the absent indigenous subject and made it the incontrovertible point of departure for an American history that we should affirm (but for our own reasons) as ‘colonial’ rather than the anodynous ‘early’ of current choice. To the existential encounter of Indians and English that furnished this history’s first moment of truth, moreover, Kupperman’s subtitle—Facing Off—added an elemental moral referent. For the other is unknowable, Emmanuel Levinas insisted, save only that facing reveals the other’s face, hence humanity. In that instant the other becomes unconditionally our ethical responsibility, to be accepted (justice) or refused (death). Kupperman’s eyewitnesses, she finds, agreed on the ‘essential humanity’ of those they encountered, suggesting that a history of acceptances might lie muffled beneath the more familiar tale of refusals (4). Not incidentally, the suggestion plants the historian’s third marker, contingency.
We should not, though, take facing too literally: facing can occur anywhere and any time. Its morality is realized in revelation, not line of sight. Arguably, indeed, the ethics of responsibility came far closer to realization in the metropolis than on the frontier (5). And other claims for the eyewitness are as problematic. To write off metropolitan texts because they do not comport with what an eyewitness purports to ‘see’, for example, is epistemologically naïve. Who is to say that the objectives of author and eyewitness are commensurate? So also, to create a narrative that produces at its climax the moment of the eyewitness’s encounter is to pick one’s way through an array of temporal and contextual standpoints that, in different combinations, would produce different outcomes. In Sweet’s narrative, English horizons do not broaden until the 1580s. But one can frame the breadth of horizons differently by looking at them in different ways.
Ken MacMillan’s Sovereignty and Possession in the English New World exemplifies precisely the difference choice can make. In MacMillan’s hands the colonizing process is removed from the social history of settler experience and indigenous contact, and reestablished as an intellectual-doctrinal product founded upon Roman law and upon conjectural histories of English sovereign claims to an ancient North-Atlantic empire predating Iberian-Columbian landfall by a millennium. The merit is obvious. There was a colonizing impulse before there were settlements, and in self-justification and legitimation that impulse marshaled and employed what was, at its time, ‘known’. MacMillan’s considerable achievement, in other words, is to explain the expressive logic (legal, historical, textual, and iconographic) of English sovereign possession in the New World. He grasps the sense (and indeed the sensibility) conveyed in metropolitan texts and crown strategies that examined, defined, claimed, defended, mapped, and negotiated a Tudor-Stuart empire in North America. Metropolitan texts were not fantasies to be overridden by ‘experience’; nor were they adventitious reconstructions of facts established on the ground by the opportunistic adventurings of freebooters, gentry speculators and a few imaginative merchants. They fashioned an intellectually coherent order of things that began long before, persisted after, and was overall generally unaffected by the moment of the eyewitness. In the service of the crown they founded—authored and authenticated—an English Empire in the New World in a fashion not one whit less significant than the social historian’s materiality of settlers struggling in unfamiliar forests and swamps.
MacMillan’s account of English colonizing discourse is grounded on two important assertions. First, from the outset the crown was an active participant rather than passive enabler that stamped formal imprimaturs on others’ initiatives. The crown acted in its imperial capacity; it took the position that it had ‘a legal, sovereign, prerogative, and imperial obligation to authorize, supervise, protect, and proclaim its overseas holdings, particularly when faced with challenges from other European colonizing monarchs’ (p. 6). It was ‘especially concerned to ensure that its imperium, or independent and absolute sovereignty, and its dominium, or right to possess and rule territory under its jurisdiction, were fully and legally expressed’ (p. 6). Second, and related, Roman law and its derivatives, not English common law, furnished ‘the principal legal foundations’ for English claims of New World sovereignty and possession (p. 13). This is a particularly important contention. Scholars examining the role of law in early-modern transoceanic colonizing have generally described a process in which distinct European legal systems framed processes of transoceanic acquisition particular to their own vernacular practices, clashing where they competed, sharing little in common. In the English case, vernacular (common law) practice and ideology furnished a potent technology—a discourse of waste (crudely, uncultivated, deserted land) and of rightful possession by inhabitation, use and improvement—for claiming and absorbing overseas territory (6). MacMillan does not dispute the salience of common law analogies and institutions in organizing settled jurisdictions, but does question the implication that European colonizing took place in a supranational legal vacuum. International law was not invented by the Treaty of Westphalia (1648)—the laws of nature (ius naturale) and nations (ius gentium) had long provided norms of decisive importance to the ordering of supranational spaces. Roman law furnished a common vocabulary for interstate relations among sovereigns, one that historians of English colonizing have thus far tended to pay relatively little attention to, precisely because they have taken the common law to be the only legal expression of English colonizing, and have attended to the crown from a domestic common law perspective as (effectively) enabler of others’ adventures rather than imperial claimant on its own behalf. Roman law’s ‘multiple, related, and “universal” legal resources’, MacMillan argues, ‘provided the crown and its advisors with a corpus of supranational material that could help it develop legal strategies in favor of imperial pursuits’, and territorial acquisitions, ‘that would be recognized by the broader European community’ (p. 13). As this underscores, in MacMillan’s account the crucial audience in English claims to sovereignty and possession is rival European sovereigns, not indigenous possessors. His subject is not the legal mechanics of dispossession but how sovereign claims were made and with whom in mind. His achievement is to show that English New World colonizing occurred not as a halting series of ill-planned, commercially-motivated, crudely justified lunges into the unknown, but within a dense and carefully-parsed, historical-legal tradition (7).
Sovereignty and Possession makes its case in six substantive chapters. Successively, these discuss: (i) the supranational Roman Law context of sixteenth-century English and European state formation—notably the crucial distinction between internal (domestic) and external sovereignty and their differential legal means of expression, and, equally important, the dual (mental and physical) components of sovereign possession; (ii) the extraordinarily fecund geographic and historical imaginaire that, particularly in the works of John Dee, invoked an extended array of North-Atlantic territories (islands and continents) long penetrated by a millennium of English voyaging and conquest dating to an Arthurian sixth century in the comprehensive legal-historical rebuttal of Iberian claims to the American mainland north of Florida; (iii) the active exercise of royal prerogative by the crown in the significant form of letters patent authorizing successive adventurers, trading companies, and palatine proprietors to implement by occupation the crown’s rights of acquisition and distribution of claimed territories (8); (iv) the fear of European rivals in motivating colonial militarization (selection and organization of personnel, choice of settlement sites, construction of fortifications, resort to martial law) and cultivation of ‘images of dominance’ (p. 122)—all instancing judicious apprehension of interference from without at least as much as a desire to intimidate or defend against indigenous inhabitants; (v) the importance of reading maps for their strategic and political content vis-à-vis European rivals (English manuscript maps, MacMillan observes, displayed superior geographic knowledge and cartographic capacity in comparison to their printed counterparts, evidencing the desire of both crown censors—acting through the Stationers’ Company—and map makers to guard secrets while still conveying representations ‘of imperial sovereignty and territorial possession’: p. 175). MacMillan’s last chapter (vi) presents an analysis of the lengthy negotiations between 1604 and 1632 with the Iberian and the French crowns that secured their acquiescence in and recognition of the English empire in America.
It is a pity that this original and important study resorts to a rather jaded cliché to convey its author’s basic purpose—‘to bring the crown and empire back in’ (p. 7). Scholars have brought so much back in since Theda Skocpol et al pioneered the phrase twenty years ago, one wonders whether anything remains left out (9). This small infelicity notwithstanding, MacMillan’s success is considerable. The tight narrative of the first four chapters decisively plants both the crown and the discourse of imperium and dominium squarely in our field of vision. Structurally, the narrative falters slightly thereafter: Chapter Five, ‘Mapping the English Empire,’ is a fine piece of work but reads somewhat as a distinct essay, and instead of a two-page ‘Epilogue’ tacked onto the end of Chapter Six, one might have preferred a more elaborated overall conclusion. In particular it might have served the author to situate his mapping research in closer proximity to his fascinating second chapter on the geographer John Dee, for, apart from their related substance, both address questions of considerable epistemological importance: namely, the historical conditions for formation of knowledge (what knowing is, what counts as known, by whom, when), and the purposes and ends for knowledge formed. Dee’s Limits of the British Empire (prepared in manuscript, 1577–8) compiled extensive geographical and historical evidence that established a record of English presence and voyaging in the North Atlantic sufficient to ensure that the queen of England could lay claim to imperium and dominium throughout the North Islands and the American mainland ‘from Florida to the Circle Articke’—as the younger Hakluyt would put it in the Discourse of Western Planting —‘more lawfull and righte then the Spaniardes or any other Christian Princes’ (10). Later historians would of course dismiss Dee’s history—of the empire of Britain founded by Brutus, its extension by Arthurian voyaging and conquest in the sixth century, of Madoc’s American landfall in the twelfth—as absurd myth-making. Might we not instead treat Dee’s efforts as the exhibition of an expertise that established (in the strategic service of the crown) what could, at that point, be advanced as known? In other words, MacMillan’s work suggests that we consider seriously the ‘means to know’ that enabled the Limits of the British Empire to be written.
Why the actual product of Dee’s expertise was strategically significant is best addressed under the banner ‘legal pluralism’, which also is my preferred candidate for the most important substantive contribution MacMillan makes. In recent years the legal history of English colonizing has attended to legal plurality, but primarily as a situational phenomenon. Pluralism lies in the migration of regionally-specific common law cultures from England; it lies in the subsequent divergence of common law cultures—both from each other and from their English template(s)—once implanted in regionally varied New-World environments; it lies in the consequences of encounters between common law cultures and indigenous jurispractices; it lies, finally, in the comparison of English legal cultures with those of other European colonizers. From these common law pluralisms scholars have begun to tease an overarching ‘Atlantic’ common law culture that, piecemeal and inchoate, begins to become recognizable as a form of constitutionalism for the early Anglophone imperium (11). To this common law history of English colonizing, as we have seen, MacMillan adds (and Dee expresses) the further pluralism of Roman law. Historians have already established that a domestic Roman law culture was actively represented in an English civilian tradition that complemented common law, and, more generally, was enshrined in the universalist studia humanitatis of sixteenth-century humanism (12). In this study MacMillan demonstrates quite precisely how Roman law inflected English colonizing, furnishing an overall animating structure (which common law could not do) through its discourse of imperium and dominium, while also providing common terms of competition and conciliation with European rivals, all of them operating within the same intellectual structure. Dee’s Limits of the British Empire, then, becomes virtually a case study of the employment of geography and history to put this Roman law inflection into instrumental effect by establishing the whereabouts and the lineage of prior possession and intent to possess, necessary conditions of sovereignty and acquisition (13).
Amid all MacMillan’s achievements one false note sounds—his rather casual resort to the terminology of terra nullius (literally, ‘no one’s ground’) as if this too were a routine Roman law concept (for example at pp. 106, 115, 120). It is not. No one would dispute that terra nullius has been invoked by many scholars to stand for colonizers’ claims that the New World was effectively ‘empty’ of possession. But the provenance of the term is now a matter of some controversy, particularly in recent debates over English colonization of Australia in which the concept of terra nullius is bitterly contested (14).
MacMillan sources terra nullius to Justinian:
The Roman legal precedents for the acquisition of territorial sovereignty and possession of terra nullius were the most clearly expressed in Justinian’s Digest (book forty-one) and Institutes (book two), texts which all civilian lawyers in England and Europe would have studied in detail. As the drafters of [crown letters patent] were undoubtedly aware, inserting the legal language of Roman law could help to ensure that these claims would receive either acquiescence or recognition among the broader European community. The failure of the English crown to receive such concessions for its New World territories meant that its claims could continue to be subject to diplomatic entanglements and threats of belligerency (p. 106).
In fact, the words themselves appear nowhere in the Digest or the Institutes as such. Certainly in discussing acquisition under the law of nations the Digest notes that such as ‘presently belongs to no one’ may become ‘by natural reason the property of the first taker’. But the examples, grouped under the generic term ‘things’ (rerum), are virtually all animate—‘all animals taken on land, sea, or in the air, that is, wild beasts, birds and fish’. These are things that may ‘escape from our custody and return to their natural state of freedom’. When they do so, ‘they cease to be ours and are again open to the first taker’. To its pronounced emphasis on beasts, birds, and fish (also swarms of bees, which ‘are wild until we house them in hives’, but which, upon leaving, cannot be claimed as property once out of sight) the Digest adds, ‘things captured in war, islands arising in the sea, and gems, stones, and pearls found on the seashore’. Islands arising in the sea (‘a rare occurrence’) refers not to newly-discovered lands appearing on the horizon but to outcomes of geological events—volcanic or tectonic. This is the only example in the Digest of land that is res nullius and open to possession by a ‘first taker’. All other discussion of apparently new or vacant land in book forty-one deals with islands arising in rivers (‘a frequent occurrence’) created by alluvium or by natural changes in water courses, none of which can be analogized to a conception of terra nullius or of land open to possession by a first taker, in that the principle determining possession of the island is not who takes it first but the already-existing structure of ownership of adjacent or proximate land. Indeed, the term used in the Digest to refer to land is not terra but, most commonly, fundus or estate, that is land that is already the property of someone. The Digest does consider how possession of land that has been abandoned or left derelict may be lost and taken up by others, but again this is fundus—land that has been owned rather than ‘new land’ never before taken (15).
Andrew Fitzmaurice has recently identified (terra nullius as a twentieth-century latinate formulation or tag invented in the wake of the more specific term (territorium nullius (no sovereign’s land) which was itself coined by late-nineteenth-century international lawyers, Fitzmaurice argues, ‘to codify rules for the carve-up of Africa’ (16). But although a recent invention, Fitzmaurice believes (terra nullius can appropriately be used to stand in for European colonizers’ deployment of the ancient natural law conception of the first taker’s right of possession to justify their expropriations of indigenous inhabitants deemed too barbarous or uncivilized in customs and practices to manifest conceptions of property that colonizers were bound to respect. The debate is complex and—in the Australian case—furious. It is also dogged by a failure fully to distinguish between claims of sovereign possession and their basis, and property claims advanced by settlers and their basis.
If MacMillan’s excursion into the fraught world of (terra nullius seems a little ill-judged because of the plethora of debates and confusions in which the term is entangled, little of real consequence for his argument actually hangs on it. So it would be a shame if the term’s controversies were to obscure his real achievement, which is precisely to create a basis to understand the distinction in the legal technology of English colonizing between the language of sovereign possession ((imperium and (dominium) advanced in the metropolis and the language of property in land used in situ. MacMillan does this by reinserting the crown as actor into the legal narrative of English colonizing, and by establishing an overarching Roman law context for the terms of English crown claims to New World jurisdiction in competition with other European sovereign claims. His book suggests that careful study of Roman law will greatly amplify legal historians’ comprehension of the discourses of early modern English colonizing, richly embellishing a scholarship that has, hitherto, scrutinized English colonizing’s legalities more or less exclusively in common law terms.
Once we have absorbed those lessons and followed their implications perhaps we will want to return once more to Karen Kupperman’s autoptic moment. We will return better equipped to appreciate that the momentous interaction that her work has emphasized took place in an extraordinarily dense metropolitan context.
Notes
- K. O. Kupperman, Indians & English: Facing Off in Early America (Ithaca and London, 2000), p. x; and see also her Settling with the Indians: The Meeting of English and Indian Cultures (Totowa, N.J., 1980). Back to (1)
- J. W. Sweet ‘Introduction: Sea Changes,’ in Envisioning an English Empire: Jamestown and the Making of the North Atlantic World, ed. R. Appelbaum and J. W. Sweet (Philadelphia, 2005), p. 12. On truth and falsity, see J. Edwards ‘Between “Plain Wilderness” and “Goodly Corn Fields”: Representing Land Use in Early Virginia,’ in idem, pp. 217–35, at p. 234. Back to (2)
- See for example J. P. Greene, Pursuits of Happiness: The Social Development of Early Modern British colonies and the Formation of American Culture (Chapel Hill, 1988); J. W. Hurst, Law and the Conditions of Freedom in the Nineteenth-Century United States (Madison, 1956). Back to (3)
- Kupperman, Indians & English, pp. x, 239–40. For the tale of refusals, see for example R. A. Williams, Jr., The American Indian in Western Legal Thought: The Discourses of Conquest (New York and Oxford, 1990). Back to (4)
- See for example P. Karsten, Between Law and Custom: ‘High’ and ‘Low’ Legal Cultures in the Lands of the British Diaspora—The United States, Canada, Australia, and New Zealand, 1600–1900 (Cambridge, 2002); S. Banner, How the Indians Lost their Land: Law and Power on the Frontier (Cambridge, Mass, 2005). Back to (5)
- On the deployment of waste, see P. Seed, American Pentimento: The Invention of Indians and the Pursuit of Riches (Minneapolis and London, 2001), pp. 29–44. Back to (6)
- So doing, MacMillan follows, and develops, themes suggested in the work of Anthony Pagden, for example, Lords of All the World: Ideologies of Empire in Spain, Britain and France c.1500– c.1800 (New Haven, 1995), and David Armitage, for example, The Ideological Origins of the British Empire (Cambridge, 1998). Also of interest are A. Anghie, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law (Cambridge, 2004), notably pp. 1–31, and Williams, The American Indian, pp. 3–225. Back to (7)
- We should note that the letter patent—preeminent instrument of prerogative—was consistently the means of authorization for expeditions of acquisition from the Cabot patent of 1496 through to the Restoration. In addition to MacMillan, pp. 79–120, see M. S. Bilder ‘English Settlement and Local Governance’ in The Cambridge History of Law in America: Volume 1. Early America, 1580–1815, ed. M. Grossberg and C. Tomlins (Cambridge and New York, forthcoming 2008). Back to (8)
- Bringing the State Back In, ed. P. B. Evans, D. Rueschemeyer and T. Skocpol (Cambridge and New York, 1985). Back to (9)
- R. Hakluyt (the younger), Discourse of Western Planting, in The Original Writing and Correspondence of the Two Richard Hakluyts, ed. E. G. R. Taylor (London, 1935), ii. 213, and generally pp. 290–7. Back to (10)
- See M. S. Bilder, The Transatlantic Constitution: Colonial Legal Culture and the Empire (Cambridge, Mass, 2004); D. J. Hulsebosch, Constituting Empire: New York and the Transformation of Constitutionalism in the Atlantic World, 1664–1830 (Chapel Hill, 2005). Back to (11)
- B. P. Levack, The Civil Lawyers in England, 1603–1641: A Political Study (Oxford, 1973); A. Fitzmaurice, Humanism and America: An Intellectual History of English Colonisation, 1500–1625 (Cambridge and New York, 2003). Back to (12)
- For a pioneering account of legal pluralism in colonizing see L. Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900 (Cambridge and New York, 2002). Benton argues that the state-oriented law of colonizing is primarily the product of the nineteenth century’s era of high colonialism. MacMillan’s case for ‘bringing the crown ... back in’ to early-modern English New World colonizing modifies Benton’s account. Back to (13)
- See for example M. Connor, The Invention of Terra Nullius (Sydney, 2005). Back to (14)
- See for example The Digest of Justinian, Latin text edited by T. Mommsen with the aid of P. Krueger, English translation edited by A. Watson, 4 vols (Philadelphia, 1985), iv. 41.1.3, 41.1.5.2, 41.1.7.1–5, 41.1.29, 41.1.30.1–4, 41.2.3.6–7. Back to (15)
- A. Fitzmaurice, ‘The Great Australian History Wars’ [online]. [2006] [URL: http://www.usyd.edu.au/news/84.html?newsstoryid=948] [accessed 24 March 2007]. In contrast, Patricia Seed has credited the invention of terra nullius to William Blackstone in 1765, citing his Commentaries on the Laws of England. See Seed, American Pentimento, pp. 155-6, also Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures, p. 168 n. But Seed does not provide a reference to the passage she has in mind. A search of the Commentaries fails to disclose any reference to terra nullius as such, although Blackstone does refer (ii.7) to a natural right to migrate to ‘desart uninhabited countries’. On the historical usage of territorium nullius in international law, see M. F. Lindley, The Acquisition and Government of Backward Territory in International Law: Being a Treatise on the Law and Practice Relating to Colonial Expansion (London, 1926; repr. New York, 1969). Lindley’s treatise (see pp. 32–40) does not support Fitzmaurice’s contention for the origins of territorium nullius. Back to (16)
Author's Response
It is a pleasure to be invited to respond to Christopher Tomlins’s review of my book, especially when the monograph has been so positively received by such a prominent legal scholar. Tomlins has written a thoughtful and thorough review of my book that both summarizes its content and argument extremely well and offers salient criticism that can serve to move important debates forward. One can scarcely expect more of a book review, and I must thank him for his time and effort.
At the beginning of his review, Tomlins highlights one of my significant points of contention. Specifically, this is that we must return to some of the metropolitan texts that sought to justify colonial activities to the English crown and especially to the wider European community. As Tomlins points out, this ‘return’ is necessary, in part, because many historians over the past two decades have come to question the role of the metropole and ideologies of empire during the colonial period. These works, especially the stimulating and challenging writings of David Armitage and Jack P. Greene, seek either implicitly or explicitly to show that there were few ideological notions of empire in the Tudor and Stuart period and that, even if there were, the attenuated relationship between the ‘metropolitan’ centre and the ‘colonial’ peripheries meant that the former had little overall impact on the latter (1). One of the implications of this body of scholarship is the belief that if we are to understand the legal and cultural development of colonial America before 1776, we must look to on-the-ground agents, rather than the speculations and expectations of distant and largely ineffective observers from across the ocean. It is important to point out that my desire to reintegrate these intellectual metropolitan texts has been preceded recently by the work of, for example, Armitage, Michael Braddick, Andrew Fitzmaurice, Elizabeth Mancke, and Anthony Pagden (2).
I should also emphasize that my argument is not that the ‘metropolitan centre’ had greater impact in America than has been recently recognized. In general, I agree that this relationship was attenuated for all of the reasons stated by other scholars, including a weak, generally laissez-faire centralized government and strong, independent colonial councils and legislative assemblies that eschewed central authority. Instead, I argue that, for reasons associated with its historical and legal supervisory role over the entire composite monarchy, which included its American peripheries, the ‘imperial centre’ (the crown rather than the metropolis, the monarch and privy council rather than the London merchant elite and Parliament), was involved in ways that have not been well recognized by modern historians. As Tomlins has very capably summarized, the use of Roman law was required both because it (as opposed to domestic English common law) provided the only legal framework by which the crown could supervise its entire empire and because these legal resources were, generally, recognized throughout Europe.
In this precise context, my stated purpose, ‘to bring the crown and empire back in’—although, as Tomlins points out, it is a cliché—is important and central to my thesis. As I have already implied, both ‘crown’ and ‘empire’ have recently fallen out of favour. The former has done so because of the remarkable body of literature that, looking forward to the ideological origins of the American Revolution, investigates the role of Parliament rather than the crown in especially post-Restoration colonial affairs (3). The exclusion of ‘empire’ of late is the result of its overzealous and anachronistic use by past generations of historians, and because—following Armitage and others—of the belief that overseas activities until at least 1680 were colonial and commercial but not imperial. My argument is that the reintroduction of these terms (and, in the case of empire, redefinition, following Pagden and James Muldoon) is essential to a proper understanding of the legal foundations of, and justifications for, English activities in America (4). Regardless of the crown’s often indifferent attitude toward colonial activities and toward controlling a vast, hegemonic empire, from a legal viewpoint colonial affairs that were not officially and demonstrably authorized by, and taken into the perpetual protection of, a Christian, independent sovereign (that is, a person in whom was bestowed imperium), were extremely tenuous and not likely to gain recognition within the supranational community. Tomlins might also have pointed out an even more contestable cliché found in the same sentence, the now-common misappropriation of Richard White’s ‘middle ground’ (5). This was intended to indicate my central purpose of navigating between ‘imperial’ and ‘anti-imperial’ schools of historians through a process of redefinition and reconceptualization based on contemporary, rather than modern, epistemologies (p. 7). Thus, the purpose was ‘to bring the crown and empire back in’, but not to advocate an old-fashioned view of a Tudor-Stuart ‘British Empire’.
Despite an excellent overall summary of my main arguments, Tomlins has not mentioned what I consider to be one of the more important ideas. As expressed throughout the book and reiterated in detail in the final chapter, the English perception that claims to new lands could only be completed in Roman law through what I term the ‘twin tenets of animus and corpus’ (p. 181) is vital to our understanding. In order for sovereignty and possession to gain supranational acquiescence and recognition, which were essential to reduce subsequent disputes and gain a remedy at law, both mental and physical methods had to be communicated. This better explains the various methods employed by the English (letters patent, fortifications, maps), which provided legal rationale for effectively challenging, for example, the papal bull Inter caetera and the Treaty of Tordesillas. According to the English, these documents gave only a mental claim that remained incomplete until the granted territory was physically occupied. As articulated by John Dee and by the crown in its letters patent and subsequent correspondence, this was perhaps the most important and enduring aspect of English legal foundations for empire. In most diplomatic disputes between England and its European rivals (France, the Netherlands, Portugal, and Spain), the English envoys pointed out (although not always correctly or forthrightly, of course) the deficiency of one or the other of these two elements to show that claims to sovereignty and possession were incomplete.
As Tomlins rightly points out, and as is implied throughout the book, the issue of ‘knowledge’ was very important to the construction of early-modern empires and probably deserved a more sustained discussion. In the case of the English, in a manner consistent with the teachings of the studia humanitatis and made explicit in the colonial charters with the phrase ‘certain knowledge’ (pp. 106–7), knowledge was expected to precede action. The English consistently argued that one could not lay claim to what one did not know existed. Building upon the legal tenet of animus, having the mental intention to claim land also required both knowledge of its existence and deliberate rather than accidental acts. In 1604, the English directly challenged Spain’s rights to America on the grounds that Columbus had stumbled upon it by accident, ‘not guided by foresight or knowledge’ (p. 184). But, as I demonstrate in chapters 2 and 5, the communication of knowledge had to be carefully regulated by the crown in order to ensure that the indiscriminate or boastful dissemination of information did not empower other European colonizing powers. This is, perhaps, why central Elizabethan imperial texts—Dee’s Brytanici Imperii Limites and Famous and Rich Discoveries and Richard Hakluyt’s Discourse of Western Planting—and carefully-rendered maps remained in manuscript. The knowledge communicated in these documents was reserved to the crown so that it could make decisions about its empire without allowing valuable information to get into the hands of rivals. Thus, knowledge did not have to be widely communicated to be valuable and to confer a mental intention to claim sovereignty over newfound lands. To resort to another cliché, knowledge equalled power and, to quote Armitage, ‘empire was always a language of power’ (6).
Tomlins’s main criticism is over my use of the term terra nullius, a hitherto-accepted idea that, as the reviewer points out, is now heavily contested. I admit that, as it is written (and as Tomlins quotes it), the implication is that terra nullius was an explicit term in Justinian’s writings. As Tomlins points out, and as I emphasize in Chapter 6, however, Justinian’s work was never intended to provide legal justifications for taking newly discovered land. As I write,
discovery ... had a narrow and specific usage in the positive civil law. Justinian’s examples of things that were subject to ‘first taking’ included lands that were the result of alluvial changes in nature, such as ‘an island arising in the sea’ by accretion, and wild animals that had either escaped man’s custody or had never been under man’s control. Even by the end of the sixteenth century, discovery was comparatively new legal terminology for Europeans, as it had a dubious place in Roman law and was still building consensus within the ius commune and the ius gentium (p. 181).
I later point out (p. 202), following Lauren Benton and Peter Stein, that the use of Roman law, because it was intended for the Roman city state and not as a supranational legal system, was subject to various ‘discursive possibilities’ that enabled it to be used in the context of American activities (7). Thus, these references to Justinian, despite their dubious contemporary relevance, were routinely resorted to. Partly, this use was in the form of a legal fiction to provide some precedent, however slight, to ‘new’ activities; more vitally, Justinian was used as the ratio scripta (written reason) of natural law, and thus his ‘principles’ were deemed—like the Bible—living, timeless, and subject to many forms of interpretation.
Though an increasingly blunt legal instrument in light of new scholarship, the term terra nullius conveys natural law ideas that remain important to my argument. As Tomlins and Fitzmaurice point out, it is the term, and not the general ideas it communicates, that requires scrutiny. I was very careful in this study to employ contemporary rather than modern definitions of various terms, particularly ‘empire’, because it is, in part, the anachronistic use of the term that has caused the revisionist reaction. I also deliberately chose to avoid the term ‘international law’, which was coined by Jeremy Bentham in the late-eighteenth century, because it was anachronistic to this study and suggested a degree of monolithic legal thinking that did not exist in the early-seventeenth century. Instead, I chose to use ‘supranational law’ or ‘law of nations’ (p. 10, note 28), terms with more contemporary resonance that reflected the pluralistic legal languages available to early modern ‘civilians’. By entering so easily into an anachronism respecting terra nullius while deliberately avoiding other modern terms, I concede its use was ‘casual’, especially when several contemporary terms spring to mind that would have served equally well.
In respect to Tomlins’s desire for a fuller conclusion, I should point out that Chapter 6, which draws together the central themes of the book by way of two case studies (or, as I state in the introduction, ‘by way of conclusion’ [p. 15]), coupled with that chapter’s sections entitled ‘Conclusion: Toward acquiescence and recognition’ and ‘Epilogue’, to me, offer a thorough conclusion of the book’s arguments in practical and relevant ways that do not merely summarize its contents or draw broad generalizations.
I would like to end by mentioning one of the main omissions from this book. Caused partly by a concern for continuity in the narrative, partly because Native Americans were not my subject, and partly by space and time constraints, the subject of ‘conquest’, an ancient Roman law concept with significant relevance to English Atlantic affairs, was only lightly touched upon. Understanding how this term was used legally, culturally, and rhetorically, in the context of England as a conquered and conquering state, is the project to which I am now turning my attention.
Notes
- J. P. Greene, Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States, 1607–1788 (Athens, GA, 1986); D. Armitage, The Ideological Origins of the British Empire (Cambridge, 2000). Back to (1)
- A. Fitzmaurice, Humanism and America: An Intellectual History of English Colonization, 1500–1625 (Cambridge, 2003); E. Mancke, ‘Empire and State,’ in The British Atlantic World, 1500-1800, ed. D. Armitage and M. J. Braddick (Basingstoke and New York, 2002); and Mancke, ‘Negotiating an Empire: Britain and Its Overseas Peripheries, c. 1550–1780,’ in Negotiated Empires: Centers and Peripheries in the Americas, 1500-1820, ed. C. Daniels and M. V. Kennedy (London and New York, 2002); A. Pagden, Lords of All the World: Ideologies of Empire in Spain, Britain, and France, c. 1500–c. 1800 (New Haven, 1995); M. J. Braddick, State Formation in Early Modern England, c. 1550–1700 (Cambridge, 2000). Back to (2)
- For example, I. K. Steele, ‘The British Parliament and the Atlantic Colonies to 1760: New Approaches to Enduring Questions’, in Parliament and the Atlantic Empire, ed. P. Lawson (Edinburgh, 1995). Back to (3)
- J. Muldoon, Empire and Order: The Concept of Empire, 800–1800 (Basingstoke and New York, 1999). Back to (4)
- R. White, The Middle Ground: Indians, Empire, and Republics in the Great lakes Region, 1650–1815 (Cambridge, 1991). Back to (5)
- Armitage, Ideological Origins, p. 29. Back to (6)
- L. Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900 (Cambridge, 2002); P. Stein, Roman Law in European History (Cambridge, 1999). Back to (7)